Thomson's lamp has an on-off switch. It begins in the "off" position. At noon the switch is toggled, and the lamp comes on. Half a minute later, the switch is toggled, and the light goes off. A quarter of a minute later, the switch is toggled again, and the light comes on. And so on. There are no other switch flippings than these, and the switch survives at least until 12:01 pm. At 12:01 pm, is the switch on or off?
As paradoxes go, this one seems really flimsy. As best I can see, the argument to a paradox is something like this:
- Time is actually infinitely subdivided.
- If time is actually infinitely subdivided, the story of Thomson's lamp is possible.
- Necessarily, if the story is true, then the switch is either on or off at 12:01.
- Necessarily, if the story is true, then the switch is not on at 12:01.
- Necessarily, if the story is true, then the switch is not off at 12:01.
There are a couple of ways of showing what's wrong with the argument. Here is one. In order to argue for (4) and (5), it needs to be a part of the story that
- At each time t after noon, the position of the switch is the result of the last switch-flipping event prior to t.
Fine, then, says the paradoxer: Add (6) to the story.
However, now (2) becomes false. The defender of actually infinitely subdivided time can simply deny (2), since the story is plainly inconsistent: the position of the switch at 12:01 is determined by the last flip before 12:01, but there is no last flip before 12:01. It is a story as plainly inconsistent as this one: "Whether there is an obligatory side of the street to drive on is determined by the content of the will of the king of France. And France is a monarchy." The question of the position of the switch is rather like asking: "If atheism were true, would God want us to be atheists?"
Perhaps the paradoxer will say that that was her whole point, but nonetheless the defender of actually infinitely subdivided time has to affirm that this inconsistent story is possible. But why? It is an easy game to construct inconsistent stories by including a stipulation that something is sufficient to determine something, and then adding to the story something that denies the existence of the determiner. In addition to my present king of France story, consider this one:"A lamp with an on-off switch that can only have two positions, on and off, is produced ex nihilo by God at t0. The position of the switch at any time is fully determined by how it has last been flipped." Then ask: What is the position of the switch at t0? Obviously, we have an inconsistency in the story—if the lamp came into existence ex nihilo at t0 it came into existence with the switch in a particular position, but that position was not determined by a flipping.
But does not the defender of actually infinitely subdivided time think that a lamp switch's being flipped in the supertask way is possible? Certainly. But she has to hold that this is only possible in those worlds in which either something other than the last flip determines the position of the switch at 12:01 or the Principle of Sufficient Reason is violated (I don't think there are any such) or both.
Why does the argument to a paradox have to maintain (2)? Why can't she just maintain:
ReplyDelete(2') If time is infinitely subdivisible, the story of Thomson's lamp is possible?
"Infinitely subdividable" is ambiguous. In one sense, it means that it is possible for time to be in fact infinitely subdivided. In that sense, (2') is enough. In another sense, it means that for any finite division, a further finite subdivision is possible, but without a claim that an infinite subdivision is possible. In that sense, (2') is not enough.
ReplyDelete