Williamson gave a lovely argument that infinitesimals can't capture the probability of an infinite sequence of heads in fair independent trials: Let Hn be the event that we have heads in each of the trials n,n+1,n+2,.... Then, P(H1)=(1/2)P(H2). But P(H1)=P(H2) since they're both just the probability of getting an infinite sequence of heads. Thus, P(H1)=(1/2)P(H1) and so P(H1) is zero, not infinitesimal.
It turns out that a somewhat similar result holds for Popper functions as well. For technical reasons, I need a bidirectionally infinite sequence of coin tosses, one for each integer (positive, zero or negative). Our probability space Ω of infinite sequences will then be the set of all functions from the integers Z to {H,T}. Let G be the group of transformations of Ω generated by translations defined by reflections on Z. In other words, G is generated by the transformations Ra, where a is an integer or a half-integer, and (Ras)(n)=s(2a−n) for any sequence s in Ω.
Let F be any G-invariant field in Ω that contains all the Hn. A very plausible symmetry condition on the Popper function on Ω representing the double sequence of heads then is:
- For any g in G and any A and B in F, P(A|B)=P(gA|gB).
A second obvious condition is that the probability of getting heads on tosses 1,2,3,... given that one has heads on 2,3,... is equal to the probability of getting heads on toss 1, i.e., is 1/2:
- P(H1|H2)=1/2.
Theorem: There is no Popper function on F satisfying (1) and (2).
You mean there's no proper Popper function.
ReplyDeleteIn fact, you could say that infinite sequences are Popper stoppers.
Minor improvement: you can map a unidirectionally infinite sequence (0, 1, 2 ...) onto a bidirectionally infinite sequence. So your result holds for unidirectionally inifinite sequences too.
ReplyDeleteA paper containing this result has just been accepted by the Journal of Philosophical Logic.
ReplyDelete