Tuesday, July 2, 2024

Do we have normative powers?

A normative power is supposed to be a power to directly change normative reality. We can, of course, indirectly change normative reality by affecting the antecedents of conditional norms: By unfairly insulting you, I get myself to have a duty to apologize, but that is simply due to a pre-existing duty to apologize for all unfair insults.

It would be attractive to deny our possession of normative powers. Typical examples of normative powers are promises, commands, permissions, and requests. But all of these can seemingly be reduced to conditional norms, such as:

  • Do whatever you promise

  • Do whatever you are validly commanded

  • Refrain from ϕing unless permitted

  • Treat what you are requested as a reason for doing it.

One might think that one can still count as having a normative power even if it is reducible to prior conditional norms. Here is a reason to deny this. I could promise to send you a dollar on any day on which your dog barks. Then your dog has the power to obligate me to send you a dollar, a power reducible to the norm arising from my promise. But dogs do not have normative powers. Hence an ability to change normative reality by affecting the antecedents of a prior conditional norm is not a normative power.

If this argument succeeds, if a power to affect normative reality is reducible to a non-normative power (such as the power to bark) and a prior norm, it is not a normative power. Are there any normative powers, then, powers not reducible in this way?

I am not sure. But here is a non-conclusive reason to think so. It seems we can invent new useful ways of affecting normative reality, within certain bounds. For instance, normally a request comes along with a permission—a request creates a reason for the other party to do the requested action and while removing any reasons of non-consent against the performance. But there are rare contexts where it is useful to create a reason without removing reasons of non-consent. An example is “If you are going to kill me, kill me quickly.” One can see this as creating a reason for the murderer to kill one quickly, without removing reasons of non-consent against killing (or even killing quickly). Or, for another example, normally a general’s command in an important matter generates a serious obligation. But there could be cases where the general doesn’t want a subordinate to feel very guilty for failing to fulfill the command, and it would be useful for the general to make a new commanding practice, a “slight command” which generates an obligation, but one that it is only slightly wrong to disobey.

There are approximable and non-approximable promises. When I promise to bake you seven cookies, and I am short on flour, normally I have reason to bake you four. But there are cases where there is no reason to bake you four—perhaps you are going to have seven guests, and you want to serve them the same sweet, so four are useless to you (maybe you hate cookies). Normally we leave such decisions to common sense and don’t make them explicit. However, we could also imagine making them explicit, and we could imagine promises with express approximability rules (perhaps when you can’t do cookies, cupcakes will be a second best; perhaps they won’t be). We can even imagine complex rules of preferability between different approximations to the promise: if it’s sunny, seven cupcakes is a better approximation than five cookies, while if it’s cloudy, five cookies is a better approximation. These rules might also specify the degree of moral failure that each approximation represents. It is, plausibly, within our normative authority over ourselves to issue promises with all sorts of approximability rules, and we can imagine a society inventing such.

Intuitively, normally, if one is capable of a greater change of normative reality, one is capable of a lesser one. Thus, if a general has the authority to create a serious obligation, they have the authority to create a slight one. And if you are capable of both creating a reason and providing a permission, you should be able to do one in isolation from the other. If you have the authority to command, you have the standing to create non-binding reasons by requesting.

We could imagine a society which starts with two normative powers, promising and commanding, and then invents the “weaker” powers of requesting and permitting, and an endless variety of normative subtlety.

It seems plausible to think that we are capable of inventing new, useful normative practices. These, of course, cannot be a normative power grab: there are limits. The epistemic rule of thumb for determining these limits is that the powers do not exceed ones that we clearly have.

It seems a little simpler to think that we can create new normative powers within predetermined limits than that all our norms are preset, and we simply instance their antecedents. But while this is a plausible argument for normative powers, it is not conclusive.

5 comments:

  1. In the dog case, it seems to me equivocal to say that the dog is obligating me; in particular, it is equivocating between obligation and title. The dog's barking is the title for your right to be paid, because of the structure of the norm; but the dog is not creating a norm anymore than the paper and ink on which a deed is written is creating a norm -- the relevant norm in the former case is the promise, and in the latter case the law, both of which seem to be made directly by human beings using language. While it is true that merely being a cause affecting title is not a normative power, this is because titles are not norms, but elements of a situation that tell us that the situation is one to which the norm is relevant for action.

    An argument against normative powers based on conditional norms seems too indiscriminate; for instance, here is a conditional norm with a non-normative antecedent:

    (A) If you create a norm, treat it as a norm.

    But this conditional norm seems to presuppose that we have normative powers of some kind. What the anti-normative-powers person has to argue is that conditional norms like "Do whatever you promise" are not like (A); but the dog argument certainly does not do that.

    ReplyDelete
  2. I wonder if the question you are asking might wind up being equivalent to asking whether all of the norms that bind us are grounded in our nature (including our nature as rational beings) or whether there are some norms that bind us which are grounded in specific acts of the will. If the former, then the norms that bind us would be analogous to deterministic physical laws. And we would say that human beings do not have the power to “directly” change normative reality. If the latter, then the natural norms that bind us would be analogous to indeterministic physical laws, while the free-will norms that bind us would be analogous to a Common Law system. And we would say that human beings do have the power to “directly” change normative reality.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Brandon:

    Doesn't (A) have a normative antecedent, in that it makes reference to a norm?

    Matthew:

    I worry about your formulation in that even if we take the conditional norm view, it seems correct to say that some norms are grounded in acts of the will. For instance, if I promise that I will pay you a dollar each time I perform act of will X, then after I perform act X, I am obligated to pay you a dollar, and this norm is grounded in my performance of X.

    Maybe what we should ask is whether there are some normatively fundamental norms that are grounded in acts of will. (A normatively fundamental norm is one that is not grounded in any further norm.) My obligation to pay you a dollar in my example is grounded in a further norm--the norm of keeping promises--and hence is not normatively fundamental.

    (If only normatively fundamental norms count as norms, then your question is equivalent to mine.)

    ReplyDelete
  4. (A) refers to an act of promising, not a norm of what to do with respect to acts of promising, so it's not what we would normally think of as a normative antecedent. If, however, we interpret 'normative antecedent' to mean, 'an antecedent that refers in any way to something that can be considered a norm', then virtually all antecedents that could be relevant to this kind of argument will be normative in this way, and likewise all or almost all such conditional norms could be translated into conditionals that presuppose normative powers, which would make the same point: conditional norms are too indiscriminate to do the work that the opponent of normative powers would seem to want them to do. You can easily make conditional norms that make sense but are most naturally understood as presupposing the existence of our normative powers; the opponent needs to show reductions that involve conditional norms that are specifically not of this sort.

    ReplyDelete
  5. Maybe there are some unstated assumptions here, but what is normative reality? A lot of the remarks here seem to treat people as having what strike me as mysterious, almost supernatural powers to “create” reasons and obligations other things in a literal sense. But I’m not sure why I’d think there is any distinctive, irreducible normative reality and that people have powers related to it.

    ReplyDelete