Thursday, October 24, 2024

An impartiality premise

In an argument that David Lewis’s account of possible worlds leads to inductive skepticism, I used this premise:

  1. If knowing that x is F (where F is purely non-indexical and x is a definite description or proper name) does not epistemically justify inferring that x is G (where G is purely non-indexical), then neither does knowing x is F and that x is I (now, here, etc.: any pure indexical will do) justify inferring that x is G.

This is less clear to me now than it was then. Self-locating evidence might be a counterexample to this principle. I know that the tallest person in the world is the tallest person in the world. But suppose I now learn that I am the tallest person in the world. It doesn’t seem entirely implausible to think that at this point it becomes reasonable (or at least more reasonable) to infer that the number of people in the world is small. For on the hypothesis that the number of people is small, it seems more likely that I am the tallest than on the hypothesis that the number of people is large. (Compare: That I won some competition is evidence that the number of competitors was small.)

But I think I can fix my argument by using this premise:

  1. If knowing that x is F (where F is purely non-indexical and x is a definite description or proper name) and that a uniformly randomly chosen person (or other occupied location) is x would not epistemically justify inferring that x is G (where G is purely non-indexical), then neither does knowing x is F and that x is I (now, here, etc.: any pure indexical will do) justify inferring that x is G.

There are multiple versions of (b) depending on how the random choice works, e.g., whether it is a random choice from among actual persons or from among possible persons (cf. self-sampling vs. self-indication).

It takes a bit of work to convince oneself that the rest of the argument still works.

No comments:

Post a Comment