Showing posts with label concurrence. Show all posts
Showing posts with label concurrence. Show all posts

Monday, April 21, 2025

More on God causing infinite regresses

In my previous two posts I focused on the difficulty of God creating an infinite causal regress of indeterministic causes as part of an argument from theism to causal finitism. In this post, I want to drop the indeterministic assumption.

Suppose God creates a backwards infinite causal regress of (say) chickens, where each chicken is caused by parent chickens, the parent chickens by grandparent chickens, and so on. Now, I take it that the classical theist tradition is right that no creaturely causation can function without divine cooperation. Thus, every case where a chicken is caused by parent chickens is a case of divine cooperation.

Could God’s creative role here be limited to divine cooperation? This is absurd. For then God would be creating chickens by cooperating with chickens!

So what else is there? One doubtless correct thing to say is this: God also sustains each chicken between its first moment of life and its time of death. But this sustenance doesn’t seem to solve the problem, because the sustenance is not productive of the chickens—it is what keeps each chicken in existence after it has come on the scene. So while there is sustenance, it isn’t enough. God cannot create chickens by cooperating with chickens and by sustaining them.

Thus God needs to have some special creative role in the production of at least some of the chickens, fulfilling a task over and beyond cooperation and sustenance. Furthermore, this special task must be done by God in the case of an infinite number of the chickens, since otherwise there would be a time before which that task was not fulfilled—and yet God created infinitely the chickens before that time, too, since we’re assuming an infinite regress of chickens.

What happens in these cases? One might say is that in these special cases, God doesn’t cooperate with the parent chickens. But since no creaturely causation happens without divine cooperation, in these cases the parent chickens don’t produce their offspring, which contradicts our assumption of the chickens forming a causal regress. So that won’t do.

So in these cases, we seem to have two things happening: divine cooperation with chicken reproduction and divine creation of the chicken. Since divine cooperation with chicken reproduction is sufficient to produce the offspring, and divine creation of the chicken is also sufficient, it follows that in these cases we have causal overdetermination.

Now, we have some problems. First, does this overdetermination happen in all cases of chicken reproduction or only in some? It doesn’t need to happen in all of them, since it is overdetermination after all. But if it happens only in some, then it is puzzling to ask how God chooses which cases he overdetermines and which he does not.

Second, when there is overdetermination, the overdetermination is not needed for the effect. So it seems that if God’s additional role is that of overdetermining the outcome, that role is an unnecessary role, and the chickens could be produced by mere divine cooperation, which we saw is absurd. This isn’t perhaps the strongest of arguments. One might say that while in each particular case the overdetermining divine creative action is not needed, it is needed that it occur in some (indeed, infinitely many) cases.

Third, just as it is obviously absurd if God creates chickens merely by cooperating with chickens, it seems problematic, and perhaps absurd, that God creates chickens merely by cooperating with chickens and overdetermining that cooperation.

Famously, Aquinas thinks that God could have created an infinite regress of fathers and sons, and hence presumably of chickens as well. At this point, I can think of only one plausible way of getting Aquinas out of the above arguments, and it’s not a very attractive way. Instead of saying that God cooperates with the production of offspring, we can say that occasionalism holds in every case of substantial causation, that all causation of one substance’s existence by another is a case of direct divine non-cooperative causation, with the creaturely causation perhaps only limited to the transmission of accidents. Like all occasionalism, an occasionalism about substance causation is unappealing philosophically and theologically.

Saturday, April 19, 2025

From theism to causal finitism

Causal Finitism—the thesis that nothing can have an infinite causal history—implies that there is a first cause, and our best hypothesis for what a first cause would be is God. Thus:

  1. If Causal Finitism is true, God exists.

But I think one can also argue in the other direction:

  1. If God exists, Causal Finitism is true.

Aquinas wouldn’t like this since he thought that God could create a per accidens ordered backwards-infinite causal series.

In this post, I want to sketch an argument for (2). The form of the argument is this.

  1. God cannot create a sequence of beings ..., A−3, A−2, A−1, A0 where each being causes the next one.

  2. If God cannot create such a sequence, such a sequence is impossible.

  3. The best explanation of the impossibility of such a sequence is Causal Finitism.

Claim (4) comes from omnipotence. Claim (5) is I think the weakest part of the argument. Causal Finitism follows logically from the conjunction of two theses, one ruling out backwards-infinite causal chains and the other ruling out infinite causal cooperation (a precise statement and a proof is given in Chapter 2 of my Infinity book). But I am now coming to think that there is a not crazy view where one accepts the anti-chain part of Causal Finitism but not the anti-cooperation part. However, (a) the main cost of Causal Finitism come from the anti-chain part (the anti-chain part is what forces either a discrete time or a discrete causal reinterpretation of physics), (b) there are significant anti-paradox benefits to maintaining the anti-cooperation part, and (c) the theory may seem more unified in having both parts.

Now let’s move on to (3). Here is an argument. Say that an instance of causation is chancy provided that the outcome has a probability less than one.

  1. If God can create a backwards-infinite causal sequence of beings, he can create a backwards-infinite chancy causal sequence of beings as the only thing in creation.

  2. Necessarily, if God creates a backwards-infinite chancy causal sequence of beings as the only thing in creation, then there is no creature x such that God determines x to exist.

  3. Necessarily, if God creates, he acts in a way that determines that something other than God exists.

  4. Necessarily, if God determines that something other than God exists then there is a creature x that God determines x to exist.

  5. Necessarily, if God creates a backwards-infinite chancy causal sequence of beings, then there is a creature x such that God determines x to exist. (8,9)

  6. Hence, God cannot create a backwards-infinite chancy causal sequence of beings. (7,10)

  7. Hence, God cannot create a backwards-infinite causal sequence of beings. (6,11)

The thought behind (6) is an intuition about modal uniformity. I think (6) is probably the most vulnerable part of the argument, but I don’t think it’s the one Aquinas would attack. What I think Aquinas would attack would most likely be (7). I will get to that shortly.

But first a few words about (8). In theory, it is possible to determine that something exists without determining any particular thing to exist. One can imagine a being with a chancy causal power such that if it waves a wand necessarily either a bunny or a pigeon is caused to exist, with the probability of the bunny being 1/2 and the probability of the pigeon being 1/2. But God is not like that. God’s will is essentially efficacious and not chancy. God can play dice with the universe, but only by creating dice. Thus, if God wanted to ensure there is a bunny or a pigeon without ensuring which specific one exists, he would have to create a random system that has chancy propensities for a bunny and for a pigeon and that must exercise one of the two propensities.

In fact, I think divine simplicity may imply this. For by divine simplicity, any two possible worlds that differ must differ in something outside God. Now consider a world w1 where God determines a bunny to exist, and a world w2 where God merely determines that a bunny or a pigeon exists and in fact a bunny is what comes about. There seems to be no difference outside God between these two worlds (one might wonder about the relation of being-created: could there be an relation of being-created-chancily and being-created-non-chancily? this seems fishy to me, and suggests a regress—how are the two relations differently related to God? and do we want to multiply such relations, saying there is such a thing as being-created-chancily-with-probability-0.7?). If both worlds are possible, by divine simplicity they must be the same, which is absurd. So at least one must be impsosible. And w2 is a better candidate for that than w1.

That still doesn’t establish (8). For I admitted that God can play dice if he creates dice. Thus, it seems that God could determine that something exists without determining where it’s A or B or C (say) by determining there to be dice that decide whether A or B or C are produced. But on this story, God still determines there to be dice, so there is an x—a die—that God determines to exist. I think a bit more could be said here, but as I said, I don’t think this is the main thing Aquinas would object to.

Back to (7). Why can’t God create a chancy backwards-infinite causal sequence while determining some item An in it to exist? Well, the sequence is chancy, so the probability that An − 1 causes An given that An − 1 exists is some p < 1. But, necessarily, if one creature causes another, it does so with divine cooperation (Aquinas will not disagree), and conversely if God cooperates with one creature to cause another, the one creature does cause the other. That the probability that God cooperates with An − 1 to cause An is equal to the probability that An − 1 causes An, because necessarily one thing happens if and only if the other does. Thus, the probability that God cooperates with An − 1 to cause An, given that An − 1 exists, is p. But p < 1, so it sure doesn’t look like a case of God determining An to exist!

But perhaps there is something like overdetermination, but between determination and chanciness (so not exactly over-determination). Perhaps God both determines An to exist and chancily cooperates with An − 1 to produce An. One problem with this hypothesis is with divine simplicity: it does not seem that there is any difference outside God between a world where God does both and God merely cooperates or concurs. But Aquinas may respond: “Yes, exactly. Necessarily, when one creature chancily causes another, God’s primary causation determines which specific outcome results. Thus there is no world where God merely cooperates.” So now the view is that whenever we have chancy causation, necessarily God determines the outcome. But suppose I chancily toss a coin, and it has chance 1/2 of heads and chance 1/2 of tails. Then on this view, I get heads if and only if God determines that I get heads. Hence the chance that God determines I get heads is 1/2. But it seems plausible that God’s determinations are not measured by numerical probabilities, and in any case that they are not measured by numerical probabilities coming from our world’s physics!

Tuesday, November 2, 2021

Two theories of divine conservation

Here are two theories of divine conservation, tendentiously labeled:

  • Occasionalist conservation: That a creature that previously existed continues to exist is solely explained by God’s power.

  • Concurrentist conservation: That a creature that previously existed continues to exist is explained by God’s power concurring with creaturely causal powers (typically, the creature’s power to continue to exist).

It is usual in classical theism to say that divine conservation is very similar to divine creation. This comparison might seen to favor occasionalist conservation. However, that is not so clear once we realize that classical theism holds that all finite things are created by God, and hence creation itself comes in two varieties:

  • Creation ex nihilo: God creates something by the sole exercise of his power.

  • Concurrentist creation: God creates things by concurring with a creaturely cause.

Most of the objects familiar to us are the product of concurrentist creation. Thus, an acorn is produced by God in concurrence with an oak tree, and a car inconcurrence with a factory. (The human soul is an exception according to Catholic tradition.)

Because of this, even if we opt for concurrentist conservation, we can still save the comparison between conservation and creation, as long as we remember that often creation is concurrentist creation.

Which of the two theories of conservation should we prefer?

On general principles, I think we have some reason to prefer concurrentist conservation, simply because it preserves the explanatory connections within the natural world better.

However, if we insist on presentism, then we may be stuck with occasionalist conservation, because presentism makes cross-time causal relations problematic.

[Edited Nov. 4 2020 to replace "cooperation" with the more usual term "concurrence".]

Tuesday, December 16, 2014

Existence, eternalism, continuous creation and concurrence

The doctrine of continuous creation is something like this:

  1. For all x and t, if x is a creature and x exists at t, then x is created or preserved by God at t.
On the other hand, the doctrine of concurrence is something like this:
  1. God causally concurs in every instance of creaturely causation,
where the exact details of concurrence need to be spelled out, but it is some sort of causal cooperation in or causal responsibility for the instance of creaturely causation. Given the auxiliary hypothesis that:
  1. For all x and t, if x is a creature and x exists at t, then either x is created or preserved by God at t or x is created or preserved by a creature at t,
we have a somewhat handwaving argument from (2) to (1), namely an argument that given (2), when the second disjunct in (3) holds, so does the first. For suppose that x is created or preserved by a creature at t. Then by (2), God concurs in this. But if God concurs in creation or preservation, then God creates or preserves (albeit non-solitarily).

In the literature, (2) is seen as a stronger and more controversial claim than (1), and the above argument vindicates this.

Interestingly, given eternalism, there is an argument—albeit rather handwavy—from (1) to (2).

Start with this observation: Given eternalism, existing in 2014 is rather like existing in Waco. It isn't a case of existence simpliciter, but is simply the possession of a locational property. (Given endurantism, to exist in 2014 is like being wholly present in Waco; given some four-dimensionalist theorys, it's like being partly present in Waco; but on all the theories there is a close analogy.)

Now, according to (1), when x exists at t, God is causally responsible for this. But it is strange and ad hoc given eternalism to think God is causally responsible for temporally locational properties, but not for spatially locational ones, nor for other non-privative properties. So it is very plausible that:

  1. If God is causally responsible for every case of a creature's possession of temporal location, then God is causally responsible for every case of a creature's possession of a non-privative accidental property.
But:
  1. Every instance of creaturely causation is the causation of the possession of non-privative accidental properties or the causation of existence.
And it seems that it is "metaphysically harder" to cause existence than to cause the possession of an accidental property, so:
  1. If God concurs in every case of the creaturely causation of the possession of non-privative accidental properties, then God concurs in every case of the creaturely causation of existence.
From (4), (5) and (6), we conclude that if (1) is true, then given eternalism we have God concurring in every instance of creaturely causation, and so we have (2).

This argument is handwavy, but it does show that it is ad hoc to hold on to (1) but deny (2).