Aquinas says that when a starving person takes food needed for
survival from someone who has too much, the act is a case of taking
but not stealing. Aquinas’ reasoning is that property rights
subserve survival, and in case of conflict the property rights cease,
and the food ceases to be the property of the one who has too much, and
so it is not theft for the poor to take it.
I think what is going on may be a bit more subtle than that. Suppose
Alice and Bob both have too much and Carl is starving. Both Alice and
Bob refuse their surplus to feed Carl. According to Aquinas’ analysis,
both Alice and Bob lose their ownership.
But I think things may be a bit more subtle than that. Suppose that
shortly after Alice and Bob’s wrongful refusal, Carl suddenly wins the
lottery. It does not seem right to say that Carl can now take
Alice and Bob’s surplus. Yet if Alice and Bob lost their ownership upon
refusal to feed Carl, then either the surplus now belongs to Carl or it
belongs to nobody, and in either case it wouldn’t be stealing from Alice
and Bob for Carl to take it. Similarly, if after Carl’s lottery win,
Alice were to take Bob’s surplus food, Alice would be stealing from
Bob.
We could say that Alice and Bob regain their property when Carl wins
the lottery, but it is strange to think that something that belongs to
nobody or to Carl suddenly becomes Alice’s, despite Alice having no deep
need of it, just because Carl won the lottery.
Here is a different kind of case that I think may shed some light on
the matter. As before, suppose Alice has a surplus. Suppose Eva the
mobster has informed David that if David doesn’t take Alice’s surplus,
then Eva will murder Alice. Any reasonable person in Alice’s place would
agree to having her surplus taken by David, but Alice is not a
reasonable person. David nonetheless takes Alice’s surplus, thereby
saving her life.
I think David acts rightly, precisely because as Aquinas thinks one
needs to resolve a conflict between property and life in favor of life.
But I don’t think we can analyze using Aquinas’ loss of ownership
account. For if David takes Alice’s stuff, then Eva who made David do it
is a thief (by proxy). But if under the circumstances Alice loses her
ownership, then Eva is not a thief. I think the right thing to say is
that Alice retains her ownership, but it is not wrong for David to take
her stuff in order to save her life.
What should we say, then? Is David a thief, but a rightly acting
thief? That is indeed one option. But I prefer this one. When you own
something, that gives you a set of rights over it and against others. I
suggest that these rights do not include an unconditional right not to
be deprived of the use of the item. Specifically, there is no right not
to be deprived of the use of the item when deprivation of use is the
only way for someone’s life to be saved. This applies both in Aquinas’s
case of starvation and in my mobster case. It is not an infringement on
Alice’s ownership over her surplus when Carl takes her stuff to survive
or when David takes her stuff in order to save Alice’s life. But when
Carl’s need terminates, he does not get to then take Alice’s
stuff, as if Alice had lost ownership, and the mastermind behind David’s
taking the stuff, who unlike David isn’t acting to save Alice’s life,
is a thief.
In fact, if we think about it, it becomes obvious that there is no
unconditional right not to be deprived of the use of an owned item.
Suppose I have my car on a plot of land that I own, and I foolishly sell
you all the land surrounding the small rectangle that the car is
physically on top of. By buying the land, you deprive me of the use of
my car, barring your good will—I cannot drive the car off the rectangle
without trespass. But you don’t steal my car by thus depriving me of its
use.
Thus, neither Carl (when in need) nor David is stealing, even though both take something owned by someone else.
Aquinas quotes St. Ambrose with approval: “It is the hungry man’s
bread that you withhold, the naked man’s cloak that you store away, the
money that you bury in the earth is the price of the poor man’s ransom
and freedom.” While St. Ambrose’s sentiment is very plausibly correct,
on my account above it is not correct to take it literally. When Alice
wrongfully withholds her surplus from starving Carl, the surplus is not
literally owned by Carl. It is still owned by Alice, who has a duty to
pass ownership to Carl, and Carl in turn is permitted to use Alice’s
surplus—but it remains Alice’s, even if wrongfully so.
Indeed, here is an argument against the hypothesis that ownership
literally passes to the needy. Suppose Carl is starving, and Alice and
Bob refuse their surplus. Now, shortly after Carl coming to be starving,
so does Fred. On an account on which ownership literally passes to the
needy, Alice’s and Bob’s surplus belongs to Carl, and if Carl comes to
claim it and at the same times so does Fred, Carl gets to defend that
surplus, violently if necessary, from Fred, as long as that surplus is
all needed for Carl’s survival. But it seems plausible that as long as
Carl’s and Fred’s need is now equal, they have equal rights, even if
Carl came to be needy slightly earlier. Furthermore, suppose Alice has ten loaves of
bread and Carl needs one to survive. Which loaf of bread
becomes Carl’s possession? Surely not all of them, and surely no
specific one. It seems better to say: while Carl is in dire need, Alice has no right to withhold surplus from her. As soon as Carl and any other needy person has taken enough not to be in dire need, Alice may defend the rest of her surplus.