Consider the following variant of the argument from hiddenness:
If God exists, no mature human is ignorant of God’s existence through no fault of their own.
Some mature humans are ignorant of God’s existence through no fault of their own.
So, God doesn’t exist.
It’s occurred to me that premises like (3) are either nonsense, or trivially false, or far beyond our capacity to know to be true.
For to evaluate whether some x is ignorant of God’s existence through no fault of their own requires asking something like this:
- Would x still have been ignorant of God’s existence had x lived a morally perfect life?
But it does not seem likely that there is a sensible positive answer to (4). Here is a quick argument for this. Those who deny Molinism are going to say that either the proposition asked about in (4) has no truth value or that it is trivially false. And even some Molinists will say this about (4), because Molinists are committed to there being conditionals of free will only when the antecedent is maximally specified, while “x lived a morally perfect life” is too unspecified. The question is much like:
- Had Napoleon been born in South America, would he still have been a great military leader?
There are many ways for Napoleon to have been in South America, and they are apt to result in different answers to the question about whether he was a great military leader.
But even if (4) has a truth value, perhaps because (4) is to be interpreted in some probabilistic way or because we have an expansive version of Molinism that makes (4) make sense, it is far beyond our epistemic powers to know the answer to (4) to be true. Here is why. Our lives are full of wrongdoing. Our lives would likely be unrecognizable had they been morally perfect. To ask what we would have thought and known in the counterfactual scenario where we live a morally perfect life is to ask about a scenario further from actuality than Napoleon’s being born in South America.
Now, that said, there are times when we can evaluate counterfactuals that involve a massive change to the antecedent on the basis of certain generalities. For instance, while we have no answer to (5), we do have a negative answer to:
- Had Napoleon suffered a massive head injury rendering him incapable of interpersonal communication, would he still have been a great military leader?
Similarly, if an atheist had suffered a head injury removing the capacity for higher level thought, the shape of their life would have been very different, but at least we can say that they wouldn’t have been an atheist, because they wouldn’t have had the concepts necessary to form the belief that there is no God. So, indeed, sometimes counterfactuals that take us far afield can be evaluated sensibly on general grounds.
But I do not think we have good general grounds for a positive answer to (4), unless we have independent grounds to doubt the truth and rationality of theism:
There are no good grounds for reasonably believing in God, and a person who lives a morally innocent life won’t believe things groundlessly, so they won’t believe in God.
There are people who grow up in societies where there is no concept of God, and they would not be aware of God no matter what the shape of their lives would have been.
Obviously, (7) requires independent grounds to doubt the rationality of theism. And if God exists, then for all we know, he has a general practice of making those who are morally perfect be aware of him, so (8) is dubious if God exists.
Of course, an atheist might think (7) is true, but this is unlikely to be a helpful move in an argument against the existence of God. After all, similarly, a theist might think the following is true:
- God will ensure that every morally perfect mature human is aware of him.
Indeed, a typical Christian thinks that there have only ever been one or two people—Jesus and maybe Mary—who have been morally perfect, and both candidates were aware of God.